10.17.2005

Borderlands — Responsibility in a Place and Time of Terror

Topic(s): "War on Terror" | Comments Off on Borderlands — Responsibility in a Place and Time of Terror

Responsibility in a Place and Time of Terror
Rosalyn Diprose
University of New South Wales
1. On July 14, 2003, under the leading headline “The Traitors Within”, the Sydney Morning Herald outlined ways that Australia harbours a “network of terrorist sympathisers” that supports and exports “offshore extremists” (p.1). This knowledge, that covert unforeseeable aggression directed against a sovereign state is not only possible but may come from within its territory, is one defining feature of this place and time of terror; another is knowing that one’s sovereignty will be targeted but without knowing when. Knowing that one’s sovereignty is targeted but not knowing from where, whom, or when renders the borders of sovereignty and its future uncertain. It is this uncertainty of place and time that inspires and characterises terror. At the same time, certain Government-led responses to terrorism (the ‘finger-pointing’ headlines and Government policies of surveillance, exclusion, and of pre-emptive strikes against ‘outsiders’), responses that presume to know, delimit, and seek to protect the borders of sovereignty, contribute to the terror. Assuming to know what is impossible to know, the spatio-temporal borders of sovereignty and the origin of unforeseeable threats to it, can not only instil terror in those ‘outsiders’ targeted and excluded, but also in those ‘outsiders’ arising within one’s territory. Such self-certainty in a place and time of terror effects an implosion that Derrida, in Philosophy in the Time of Terror, has called an “autoimmunitary process”, where a living being “works to destroy its own protection” (Derrida 2003, 94).
2. Rather than re-tracing Derrida’s account of this “autoimmunity” I will examine the related issue of responsibility that he explicitly sets aside (2003, 98). This paper argues that the implosion from within that proliferates terror arises through the severe self-responsibility characteristic of a sovereignty that, in seeking to secure its future in advance, denies its dependence on what Levinas refers to as unassumable responsibility for the other. At the same time, as this responsibility for the other is by definition “utopian” (Levinas 1998, 216), a call from, and a movement toward, the other arising from no-place and no-time, the passivity of being given for the other that Levinas’ formula of responsibility implies could be equally terrifying. Hence, I will argue, some self-responsibility must be assumed in assuming responsibility for others. This has implications for an account of responsible government: Responsibility in a place and time of terror requires a liberal democratic politics more responsive than the Australian Government has been to its own responsibility for the proliferation of terror and to its responsibility for the ‘outsiders’ within the territory that it assumes to govern.
Community and the No-Place and No-Time of Terror
3. Tracing my Government’s responsibility requires, however, attending to my own. I do so, not because my reduced capacity to respond responsibly to 9/11 was unique, but precisely because it wasn’t; and, because tracing my own responsibility illustrates how the capacity to respond, and the affective and corporeal basis of this, is what grounds responsibility and community. A reduced capacity for responsibility and therefore community is precisely what has been fostered, censored, and left out of account in the politics surrounding the “war against terror”
4. I was outside familiar territory, in Manchester, on September 11, 2001. I was about to present a paper on politics and community framed, ironically it seems now, in terms of the Australian Government’s move to shore up the borders of its sovereign territory by preventing those 430 Afghan asylum seekers, rescued by the Tampa, from landing on its shores. Poised ready to unleash 4000 cleverly chosen words I saw, next to the registration desk, the image of the World Trade Centre hit time and time again. Over the next 24 hours as that image was repeated from every possible angle, but always ending in a pile of rubble on top of 3000 lives, it captured my eyes, tore through my skin, and left my body as an open wound. Is this wound, this sensation without sense that so many of us felt, a touch of terror? Is this the “negative pleasure” of Kant’s sublime provoked by images that exceed my powers of representation? This open wound filled out into a thickness at the back of my throat, at the top of my lungs, and behind my eyes. No clever words came to close up this wound, no jokes, no sense, no thoughts, no aesthetic ideas that would enhance moral ideas of reason, as Kant would have it. I lost my sense of humour, my “she’ll be right mate”. I felt sick, homesick, and alone. That loss of capacity for community could have been felt even if I had been home. That sense of aloneness could be the singularity, the individualisation, the “impassioned freedom” awakened by being thrown back on oneself as being one’s ownmost possibilities for existence that Heidegger says arises when confronted by the death of others that we cannot share (Heidegger 1962, s.46-53).
5. But if it was the death of unknown others that inspired this felt response this was only because those deaths arose in a socio-political context that implicated my community, my being-with others, in a way that I could not escape. For how many times before have we been exposed, via a television screen, to similar imagistic indicators of death and destruction without much affect: Rwanda, the first Gulf war, Kosovo, East Timor, and even the Tampa? From the safety of our lounge rooms we may feel reassured that we are not involved, or even compassion or concern for the targets of violence, or shame and disgust at the complicity of our own governments. But rarely do we, in middle-class Australia, witness such events in the speechless terror that accompanies a threat to sovereignty. Usually those events that the West have deemed acts of terrorism and that have punctuated my adult life – beginning with the Palestinian siege of the Israeli sector of Munich’s Olympic village in 1972 – could be expunged as having nothing to do with me. What made the images of September 11 different for me was that I could not stand outside the picture: I was immediately there as both a perpetrator and a target.
6. This exposure to the finitude of others that suggested my own, came not so much from being confronted by the death of unknown others foreign to my territory, as via the destruction of a monument to Western global imperialism of which I am a part. This was a monument to a long-standing venture both covert and overt, economic and military, that would build a world “order which is, in fact, the worst of all disorders” (Agamben 2002, 5), with no borders and no outside; a venture that does not respect sovereignty, except its own, and whose own sovereignty and force of law only become apparent when called into account. For the guardians of Western capital and of its “force of law” (Derrida 2003, 95) are elusive and irresponsible; they work in mysterious ways in extending the borders of their territory, in measuring the value and meaning of what lies within, and in deciding what counts as acceptable collateral damage in the maintenance of disordered global order. The images of the World Trade Centre being reduced to rubble, then, were not entirely without meaning for me: what they signified in what I felt was a calling into account of the guardians of Western imperialism. And if I felt for anyone beside myself on September 11 it was for the deaths of those others so easily dismissed as collateral damage: not just the deaths signified by the destruction of the World Trade Centre in the present, but also the collateral damage of the past, and mostly for the possible collateral damage in the future, which, as the images suggested, could now include me and those I know and love who live within the global shadow of the World Trade Centre. So, along with that sense of aloneness, and contrary to what Heidegger says, the thickness at the back of my throat, at the top of my lungs, and behind my eyes threw me back upon my being-with those other others whose immediate absence I so palpably felt. For, as Jean-Luc Nancy suggests, “it is through death that the community reveals itself – and reciprocally” (Nancy 1991, 14).
7. These communities, local, national, global, are formed, not by association between autonomous, free individuals who respect the same sovereign power and freedom they find, by analogy, in others. Rather, community arises from the way that, as finite or mortal beings our finitude and hence our uniqueness can only mean something of value to others. It is as bodies that we are mortal, finite, vulnerable, and make unique sense as an expression of belonging to social worlds in a way that no one has access to and, with this, as the basis of moral value. But the body’s unique sense only appears and makes sense, not as a sign of sovereignty, but by exposure, through death and through birth, to the finitude (and hence uniqueness) of other bodies in community (Nancy 1991, 28; 1993, 204). At the same time, community, and the circulation of meaning that sustains it, only arises and makes sense through the sharing and preservation of this uniqueness. A community, however large and however disordered, cannot be maintained when suffering inflicted by these elusive forces of Western imperialism strip the bodies of others of the opportunity for community. Under such conditions community, meaning, and Being will implode. In the extreme, those guardians of a disorder that is maintained by so much collateral damage may be called into account and reminded of their community and, therefore, of the effects of their imperialism, by violence in return. Then there may be no future toward which impassioned freedom extends, and no home to want to come home to. Terror: the disabling of the future and an attendant implosion of meaning and Being, not from a single event that we might call 9/11, but without a locatable origin and possibly without end.
8. Sovereign power rendered explicit in being called into question is simultaneously sovereignty wounded. In the absence of anything that can immediately heal this wound and restore sense, there is the tendency to close it over with hate, blame, retribution, and anger against those we would perceive as belonging outside the territory under attack. And I am no less guilty of this tendency than anyone else. But the menace that haunted my nightmares immediately following September 11 was not a Muslim fundamentalist with gun raised in the air. It was the Lone Ranger who, sitting tall and proud on his reared white horse, has linked the body of my community to the wild west of American culture since childhood. As the thickness at the back of my throat, at the top of my lungs, and behind my eyes turned to anger and blame it was that menace, that aspect of my being with that I tried to expunge from my territory. The rhetoric of indignation, patriotism, retribution, and war, that flowed out of George Bush’s mouth only served to fuel my anger and the blame. “No” I said to Bush’s TV image, and to Tony Blair’s as he joined the chorus, “this is not an attack on democracy and freedom but a response to the economic, military, and cultural imperialism that has been carried out in their names.”
9. Viewing this event as an attack on the freedom of the sovereign individual or a State raises the spectre of responsibility. Under the umbrella of such a notion of individual freedom, someone or something, considered equally free, can be held responsible for the action that puts my freedom under threat. As Judith Butler explains: talk of rooting out the agents of terrorism “accords with our own idea of personal responsibility” allowing a plan of retribution against an agent of terror that is “easier to hear” than an account of our “collective responsibility” for the pre-history of September 11, a pre-history of Western imperialism that contributes to the conditions that give rise to agents of terror (Butler 2002, 4 & 11-12). Armed with these ideas of responsibility and freedom the Lone Rangers of the ‘Coalition of the Willing’ hold Osama bin Laden responsible and target territories that might harbour him. Failing to find that agent in Afghanistan, and by some weird twist of logic, Saddam Hussein is held responsible and countless others as the deck of cards fall. I take the opposite, but no less easy, option and blame the US, at least initially. But holding the US solely responsible for this place and time of terror is just as dependent on a spurious notion of individual responsibility that would order, rank, and target a deck of cards.
10. And besides, it denies the Lone Ranger in me. As Anthony Burke (2001), among others, has shown, events like the Tampa symbolised the first of only the most recent of Australia’s “Pacific Solutions” to perceived threats to its territorial integrity. So, true to its history of nation-building and within weeks, Australia added its meagre forces to a Will that was set for an expression of sovereign power that Foucault, with his emphasis on disciplinary power, had not envisaged for our time and that I could not hope to escape. With the aim of protecting and reasserting its own sovereign territory, the Coalition of the Willing set about making explicit what had been largely implicit in the ordering of things: it will take responsibility only for imposing the force of law and order; in a denial of community, it will not accept responsibility for the effects of that ordering; and those who dissent or retaliate will be held responsible for disorder and the terror that this implies. That this response could only perpetuate the conditions that give rise to terror is revealed by examining more closely the pre-history, not so much of September 11 per se, but the notion of responsibility that has been evoked in attempts to heal the wound it exposed.
Self-Responsibility: From a Body Opened to a Future to Pre-emption
11. If there is such a being as the sovereign individual who is either the agent or the target of terrorism then, as Nietzsche reminds us in On the Genealogy of Morals, s/he is made rather than given. How the sovereign individual is made through the “force of law” provides some insight into the same operation of territorialisation by the forces of Western imperialism mentioned above. The notion of responsibility at issue presupposes a being who is considered the cause of their acts, can be held accountable, and so has the right to make promises and participate, by way of contract to uphold prevailing laws, in the benefits of law-governed sociality. But creating this being first of all involves time; time and meaning. If we are by nature creatures that rarely attend to impressions and barely grasp what they mean let alone attribute them to an agent in the past (whether oneself or another), then self-responsibility requires the temporalisation and signification of events. It requires the disruption of presence and the ordering of personal time into a recognisable past, present and future, all potentially accessible to the subject in the present. This temporalisation in turn requires the attaching of meaning and value to some events rather than others. Only through the codification of events can the individual recognise some events as significant and as belonging to them as opposed to events caused by someone or something else. And, most fundamentally, self-responsibility requires being open to a future with the ability to project ahead of oneself events, their meaning, and the self who owns them. In sum, self-responsibility originates, says Nietzsche, with the creation of a “real memory of the will” through a socio-political disciplinary regime and its force of law that, by ordering events and their significance, opens a gap between the decision (I will) and the future discharge of the will (the act), and a causal link between them; opens a gap between one will and another, and opens the ability to anticipate a future and, through a selective memory, to recoup in the future a past that is now present (Nietzsche GM II 1; 1967, 58). With this much Emmanuel Levinas agrees: for subjectivity, “time is needed”; there must be a “getting out of phase with the instant”; a “divergence of the identical from itself”, a divergence of the present from past and future (Levinas 1981, 28).
12. Aside from the usual tendency to emphasise the time of being in the constitution of subjectivity, Nietzsche notes that creating this responsible self also requires the constitution of the place, the territory, of responsibility. And this place of temporalisation and signification of events, and its product, is a body that can act, that has a meaningful world, and is obliged to uphold the values and laws that govern that world. The responsible agent is created through the “mnemotechnics” of pleasure and pain whereby sensations are ordered and make sense. It is by discipline of a body through the force of law that some ideas become “unforgettable” (Nietzsche GM II 3; 1967, 60-1). Not only are events (like the destruction of the World Trade Centre) and moral ideas (including the idea of responsibility) thus lived by the body, but also innocuous ideas of custom such as the idea that the sun will rise tomorrow and will be the same sun that I saw yesterday. It is the repetitious association between sensations and their social meanings that the body is both spatialised and temporalised, a futural gap opens between the body that wills, the body that acts, the body that has done, and the body of another. Insofar as a body bears the burden of meaning incorporated through its social governance, it also bears the burden of responsibility and with this a past that it can own in the present and the compulsion of a future opened in advance.
13. There are two interim points arising from this account of the constitution of the self-responsible individual. The first is that, to the extent that responsibility depends on the spatio-temporalisation of a body, this is enabled by a socio-political disciplinary system that governs the circulation of meaning, law, and value. A democratic government guiding this force of law is therefore responsible, not directly for the acts of individuals within its care, but for providing the conditions that enable bodies to be open to a future so they can thereby act and make sense. Second, it is these bodies, acting in a meaningful world and open to a future, that are at stake in the battle over responsibility between sovereign powers that refuse to be called into account for the effects of their force of law and the terror that this unleashes. It is these bodies that are undone, rendered senseless, and barred from a future in a place and time of terror. I will return to both these points.
14.. The minimal requirement then for agency, for sensibility that makes sense, is the opening of a body to a future; not a future formulated in advance, just a future per se. Responsibility, decision-making, and agency, do not rely on certain knowledge of the future but rather on “risk and …an act of faith” (Derrida 2003, 118). In assuming responsibility, the self risks itself for a future; the self “goes under” as Nietzsche puts it (eg. Nietzsche Z Prologue; 1978, 9-25). But the ideas of responsibility and freedom assumed by the Coalition of the Willing would remove this risk: it expects the preservation of its autonomy, the endurance of its image of itself, and certainty about what its future should look like. Under such conditions the self or a sovereign State is expected to be pre-emptive. The key to such a responsible will certain of the truth and goodness of its ordering of things is a “temporality of time [that] makes possible, however, a recuperation in which nothing is lost”, at least nothing of significance to the self (Levinas 1981, 28-9). As Nietzsche puts it:
To ordain the future in advance in this way, man must first have learned to distinguish necessary events from chance ones, to think causally, to see and anticipate distant eventualities as if they belonged to the present, to decide with certainty what is the goal and what the means to it, and in general be able to calculate and compute. Man himself must first of all have become calculable, regular, necessary, even in his own image of himself, if he is to be able to stand security for his own future, which is what one who promises does! (Nietzsche GM II 1; 1967, 58)
15. The question is whether and at what cost such autonomous self-responsibility is assumable, whether one’s future can be ordained in advance and recuperated in the end, and whether and at what cost an individual or a Government of a sovereign territory can claim responsibility for itself, its force of law, without taking responsibility for its effects on others. While Nietzsche is critical of how the process of spatio-temporalisation that constitutes the responsible self is normalising, (it takes place under the guidance of a “social straightjacket of moral values” and so is not genuine self-responsibility), he does think that a truly sovereign individual can emerge from this disciplinary regime in the end. This would be the individual or state who becomes its own measure of value, its own law, who is “liberated again from the morality of custom”, who is thereby autonomous, and so is a genuinely responsible and free agent with power over him/her self and his/her fate (Nietzsche GM II 2; 1967, 59-60).
16. Even if such “genuine” self-responsibility were possible it has not been manifest in agents who, as products of Western imperialism, would now seek revenge for past suffering inflicted on them; nor is it manifest in the defenders of Western sovereignty who seek retribution in response. For what characterises the genuinely sovereign individual or state, for Nietzsche, is not revenge against those who transgress its apparent integrity, but forgiveness. If the place and time of sovereignty could be secured pre-emptively through the self-legislation of meaning and value it should be secure enough to forgive transgressions of the meanings and force of law that sustain its sovereign territory (Nietzsche GM II 10; 1967, 72-3). Only the most secure, the most unified, the most self-responsible community could endure such injury “without suffering from it”; “it goes without saying,” although Nietzsche says it, “that mercy remains the privilege of the most powerful man” (Nietzsche GM II 10; 1967, 72-3). Arguably, such privilege is not enjoyed by those who have suffered under the forces of Western imperialism (although such impotence in no way justifies the events of 9/11). But given the military, economic, and codifying might of the Coalition of the Willing, why is there no sign of mercy or forgiveness from that quarter? Why does the Coalition of the Willing resort instead to the kind of justice characteristic of a half-baked responsibility; “revenge” sanctified “under the name of justice”? (Nietzsche GM II 11; 1967, 73-4)
Please visit to read the rest of this article:
http://www.borderlandsejournal.adelaide.edu.au/vol3no1_2004/diprose_terror.htm